Svoboda | Graniru | BBC Russia | Golosameriki | Facebook
Academia.eduAcademia.edu
Review of John Cooper’s Pursuits of Wisdom (for Mind) JOHN SELLARS John Cooper’s Pursuits of Wisdom offers an introduction to what he calls six ancient philosophical ways of life. The book is designed to be accessible to nonspecialists and the bulk of it is taken up with well-informed – indeed authoritative – accounts of the ethical theories of Plato’s Socrates, Aristotle, Stoicism, Epicureanism, Pyrrhonian scepticism, and Plotinian Neoplatonism. In the main these cover territory that is fairly well known already and in form they follow the usual practice of describing the central tenets of each theory. What makes this book distinctive is the claim that we ought to think of these different philosophical positions as competing ways of life. That claim is set out in the introduction, which is in many ways the most interesting and distinctive part of the book. In what follows I shall focus on two points that Cooper makes there, both of which are central to his whole approach. Cooper acknowledges that his book was inspired in part by reading the work of Pierre Hadot, which he calls ‘fundamental reading on this subject’ (p. 18). However Cooper does not embrace Hadot’s approach to ancient philosophy uncritically and in particular he distinguishes his own approach from Hadot’s in two important ways. I am inclined to agree with Cooper on one of these, but not the other. The first of these points is made plain in the subtitle to the book, Six Ways of Life in Ancient Philosophy from Socrates to Plotinus. Cooper rejects Hadot’s global claim that philosophy as such was conceived as a way of life in antiquity (p. 29). We might be able to point to particular philosophers or schools of 2 philosophy that did hold this conception of philosophy but to move from those particular cases to the generalized claim that all ancient philosophers held that conception is not one that Cooper wants to make. Instead he identifies six philosophical traditions that he thinks do embrace this approach, starting with Socrates, including Aristotle and the major Hellenistic schools, and concluding with Plotinus. Numerous other ancient philosophers are left out: the Presocratics, the later Neoplatonists, potentially some Peripatetics and Stoics more interested in what we would now call science than Socratic care of the self, and so on. For very sensible reasons he also puts Plato to one side (pp. 668). In short Cooper proposes what we might call metaphilosophical pluralism in ancient philosophy. This seems right to me and Cooper’s account offers an important corrective to Hadot’s approach to ancient philosophy. Some philosophers in antiquity conceived philosophy as a way of life, but others did not. The second point goes right to the heart of Hadot’s project. Although Cooper embraces the idea of philosophy as a way of life, he rejects the idea that ancient philosophy ought to be conceived as a spiritual exercise, or even that spiritual exercises might play any significant role in philosophy conceived this way. Cooper sees this as a later Christian idea anachronistically imposed by Hadot on earlier pagan philosophers. While I think that Cooper right to suggest that the claim that philosophy was merely a spiritual exercise is too simplistic, I do not think we need to go as far as rejecting the notion of spiritual exercise altogether. There are three points to be made. First, Cooper suggests that Seneca is the earliest person to make use of these exercises (p. 20). Putting aside the point that he was unlikely to have been influenced by burgeoning Christian practices, Seneca was in fact drawing on earlier Pythagorean practices recorded in the Golden Verses. We know that 3 earlier Stoics also wrote works on the role of exercises, even if the works themselves are lost (see e.g. Diogenes Laertius 7.166, 167). The Cynics were also known for their exercises (discussed in M.-O. Gouet-Cazé, L’Ascèse cynique, Paris: Vrin, 1986). We can also see these sorts of practices in Epicureanism, as Cooper later acknowledges (p. 402). Cooper argues that Epicurus is a special case, after having already suggested that Seneca is the exception that proves the rule. The claim that philosophical exercises are not indigenous to pagan ancient philosophy seems misplaced; the basic idea was not unusual and was fully articulated by the Roman Stoic Musonius Rufus, entirely free of Christian influence (see fr. 6 Hense). It is noteworthy that Musonius receives no mention in Cooper’s book. Second, Cooper argues that, with the exception of the Epicureans, ancient philosophers had no need of such exercises, for a broadly Socratic monistic psychology meant that there was no room for a gap between knowledge and action. I have argued elsewhere that this is not so for the thoroughly Socratic Stoics and, by extension, not necessarily so for Socrates either. Both Socrates and the Stoics draw on a medical analogy for philosophy – not merely that philosophy is a cure for the mind just as medicine is a cure for the body, but also that philosophy is like medicine a τέχνη, mastery of which requires a grasp of complex philosophical doctrine and a period of training designed to digest that doctrine. Grasp of the doctrine does not constitute knowledge, only mastery of the τέχνη. Consequently it is possible to accept the doctrine without being automatically set into action and a space for some kind of philosophical exercise remains. Beyond Socrates and the Stoics we might also note the role of habituation in Aristotelian ethics. Third, Cooper sees Hadot’s spiritual exercises as something esoteric and so consequently suspect. To this he adds: 4 a great many of the alleged “spiritual exercises” Hadot instances in his discussion of Hellenistic philosophy are no more than perfectly ordinary ways of getting oneself to understand the real meaning and implications of philosophical arguments and philosophical positions, to fix them in one’s mind and make oneself ready to apply them smoothly to situations of life as they may arise. These are parts of the intellectual training required to live philosophically; there is nothing at all “spiritual” in Hadot’s sense of the term about them. (p. 402) Here Cooper seems to bring certain preconceptions to bear on Hadot’s use of the phrase ‘spiritual exercise’. He is right to note that many of Hadot’s examples are fairly mundane practices that fit with the description he gives here. But rather than take that to point to an inconsistency on Hadot’s part, we might instead take it as contributing to how we understand Hadot’s use of the phrase. Although Hadot borrows the phrase from St Ignatius of Loyola, he uses it to point to what Musonius Rufus called ἄσκησις τῆς ψυχῆς, a fairly straightforward notion of mental training. It is true that in places Hadot does use the phrase to point to something more esoteric, primarily when discussing Neoplatonism, but his other uses of the phrase, such as the Hellenistic cases questioned by Cooper, show that Hadot’s sense of the concept was much broader than that. Cooper himself acknowledges that Hadot uses the term in both a broad way and a narrower way, and simply chooses to attribute the narrower view to Hadot (pp. 402-3). We might have equally identified the broader view as Hadot’s, a view very close to Cooper’s own. 5 In sum, then, Cooper need not be quite so concerned about the notion of spiritual exercises as he appears to be and in fact his own view is closer to Hadot on this point than he might think. A spiritual exercise is nothing more esoteric than ‘the intellectual training required to live philosophically’ that Cooper himself endorses (p. 402). Cooper is right to be wary of the claim that ancient philosophy was merely a spiritual exercise, and his book as a whole does a fine job in stressing the way in which philosophical arguments were foundational (and in some cases constitutive) for the different ways of life proposed by ancient philosophers, but there is also room to hold on to the idea of a philosophical exercise conceived as a form of mental training. Cooper’s suspicion towards the notion of spiritual exercises means that the bulk of the book focuses its attention on the details of the various ethical theories of the philosophies that he discusses. It is noteworthy, for instance, that in the chapter on Stoicism he restricts himself to the early Stoics (see p. 150), passing over the rich works of the later Roman Stoics who show in vivid detail precisely what would be involved in taking up Stoicism as a way of life. This seems like a missed opportunity given the topic of the book. Despite this, the book as a whole offers a comprehensive overview of ancient ethics that is sensitive to historical context and that tries to comprehend ancient philosophy on its own terms. Many readers will learn a lot from it.